Artistic forgery
Extrait du document
«
Artistic expression
Many kinds of psychological state can be expressed in or by works of art.
But it is the artistic expression of
emotion that has figured most prominently in philosophical discussions of art.
Emotion is expressed in pictorial,
literary and other representational works of art by the characters who are depicted or in other ways presented in
the works.
We often identify the emotions of such characters in much the same way as we ordinarily identify the
emotions of others, but we might also have special knowledge of a character's emotional state, through direct
access to their thoughts, for instance.
A central case of the expression of emotion by works of art is the
expression of emotion by a purely musical work.
What is the source of the emotion expressed by a piece of music?
While art engages its audience, often calling forth an emotional response, its expressiveness does not consist in
this power.
It is not because an art work tends to make us feel sad, for instance, that we call it sad; rather, we
react as we do because sadness is present in it.
And while artists usually contrive the expressiveness of their art
works, sometimes expressing their own emotions in doing so, their success in the former activity does not depend
on their doing the latter.
Moreover, the expressiveness achieved has an immediacy and transparency, like that of
genuine tears, apparently at odds with this sophisticated, controlled form of self-expression.
It is because art
presents emotion with simple directness that it can be a vehicle for self-expression, not vice versa.
But if
emotions are the experiences of sentient beings, to whom do those expressed in art belong if not to the artist or
audience? Perhaps they are those of a fictional persona.
We may imagine personae who undergo the emotions
expressed in art, but it is not plain that we must do so to become aware of that expressiveness, for it is arguable
that art works present appearances of emotions, as do masks, willow trees and the like, rather than outward signs
of occurrent feelings.
Expressiveness is valuable because it helps us to understand emotions in general while
contributing to the formation of an aesthetically satisfying whole.
1 The expression of emotion Thoughts and attitudes can be expressed.
My concern here, though, is with artistic
expressions of emotions, feelings and moods.
I shall consider what and whose emotions are communicated in art,
and the nature of expressiveness in art works.
Sometimes a person's expressions are distinguished from their
dispassionate reports of their emotions (because the emotion is not directly present in the utterance).
Also,
expressions might be separated from uncontrolled ventings of emotions, these latter being regarded as symptoms,
like the spots of measles, that betray or symptomize the condition without expressing it.
My own approach is more
liberal.
I count as an expression any behaviour or display that communicates the agent's emotion, feeling or mood.
Such instances of behaviour might be unintended and unthinking, or deliberate and self-conscious.
(Indeed, their
expressive character might depend on their being the one rather than the other.
If my weeping is deliberate and
controlled, this suggests pretence rather than expression; if my behaviour is unintended, then it cannot involve the
use of social conventions for expression, even if it seems to match these.) Typically, emotions depend on causal
circumstances, take intentional objects and involve beliefs and desires (or make-beliefs and make-desires)
concerning that object.
For example, I hope for peace at a time of conflict because a treaty has been signed and
because I believe treaties lead to the cessation of hostilities, which is what I desire.
A person's emotion might be
apparent to another who possesses knowledge of any suitable combination of these elements.
In some cases, a
person's nonverbal actions alone will indicate that they feel an emotion.
In fewer cases - those in which an emotion
has an unambiguous mode of nonverbal expression - actions alone might indicate that a particular emotion is
experienced.
(Perhaps only the broadest categories for happiness and sadness have patterns of behavioural
expression sufficiently distinctive for this to be the case; cognitively complex emotions, such as hope or jealousy,
have many behavioural expressions none of which is distinctive.) More often, behaviour expresses the agent's
emotions only where the wider context is known.
There are further possibilities for the communication of emotion:
one can learn of a person's emotions from true descriptions of them given by knowledgable third parties, or from
their own sincere reports.
If emotions can be individuated solely by their sensational character and the dynamic
structure of their phenomenology, one's knowledge of the detail of a person's 'internal' experience could
communicate their emotions.
Finally, note that the expression of emotion has a social, arbitrarily conventional
dimension.
In some cultures, for instance, the wearing of black clothes and veils is an expression of grief or respect
for the dead.
The relevant conventions must be followed deliberately and sincerely if the resulting actions are to
express an emotion the person feels.
2 Characters in works If the work contains characters (for example, through depiction or description), then these
characters might experience emotions to which their behaviour or circumstances give expression.
Unless the
audience is given reason in the work's contents, its genre, or the context of presentation to make-believe
otherwise, it is to assume that the beliefs, behaviour, bodily attitudes and causal circumstances of the work's world
correspond to those of the actual world.
Accordingly, the audience can learn what emotions the work's characters
experience in the same manner as it recognizes the emotions communicated by others in the ordinary world, except
that the audience's relation to the world of the work depends on make-believe rather than belief.
Some differences
are worth noting, however.
In the case of narratives written in the first person, the audience might come to know
'from the inside' what a character experiences or believes, and hence what they feel, even if that feeling is not
outwardly indicated.
Second, the protagonists might be non-human or unreal concoctions, such as elephants or
intelligent ants.
In considering the emotions of such creations, information about their point of view will be relevant
- their cognitive commitments and values, their vulnerabilities and aspirations, their intellect, physiology and the
like.
In addition, artists create expressive contexts that do not or could not arise in the actual world.
For instance,
the use of leitmotiv in opera to recall actions or words might reveal that a character's passion is meant for X
despite being directed at Y.
Quotation and reference, both within and between works, might establish an expressive
ambience one would not normally find or look for.
In addition to the emotions of their characters, art works seem to
embody and express emotions of their own.
This applies to all kinds of works but is perhaps most striking in abstract.
»
↓↓↓ APERÇU DU DOCUMENT ↓↓↓