Aristotle (384-322 BC)
Extrait du document
Aristotle was born in 384 BC, in the Macedonian city of Stagira, now part of northern Greece. In his lifetime the kingdom of Macedon, first under Philip and then under Philip's son Alexander ('the Great'), conquered both the Greek cities of Europe and Asia and the Persian Empire. Although Aristotle spent much of his adult life in Athens, he was not an Athenian citizen. He was closely linked to the kings of Macedon, whom many Greeks regarded as foreign invaders; hence, he was affected by the volatile relations between Macedon and the Greek cities, especially Athens. Aristotle was the son of Nicomachus, a doctor attached to the Macedonian court. In 367 BC Aristotle came to Athens. He belonged to Plato's Academy until the death of Plato in 347; during these years Plato wrote his important later dialogues (including the Sophist, Timaeus, Philebus, Statesman, and Laws), which reconsider many of the doctrines of his earlier dialogues and pursue new lines of thought. Since there was no dogmatic system of 'Platonism', Aristotle was neither a disciple of such a system nor a rebel against it. The exploratory and critical outlook of the Academy probably encouraged Aristotle's own philosophical growth. In 347 BC Aristotle left Athens, for Assos in Asia Minor. Later he moved to Lesbos, in the eastern Aegean, and then to Macedon, where he was a tutor of Alexander. In 334 he returned to Athens and founded his own school, the Lyceum. In 323 Alexander died; in the resulting outbreak of anti-Macedonian feeling in Athens Aristotle left for Chalcis, on the island of Euboea, where he died in 322. Aristotle married Pythias, a niece of Hermeias, the ruler of Assos. They had a daughter, also called Pythias. After the death of his wife, Aristotle formed an attachment to Herpyllis, and they had a son Nicomachus.
«
Aristotle (384-322 BC) Aristotle of Stagira is one of the two most important philosophers of the ancient world,
and one of the four or five most important of any time or place.
He was not an Athenian, but he spent most of his
life as a student and teacher of philosophy in Athens.
For twenty years he was a member of Plato's Academy; later
he set up his own philosophical school, the Lyceum.
During his lifetime he published philosophical dialogues, of which
only fragments now survive.
The 'Aristotelian corpus' (1462 pages of Greek text, including some spurious works) is
probably derived from the lectures that he gave in the Lyceum.
Aristotle is the founder not only of philosophy as a
discipline with distinct areas or branches, but, still more generally, of the conception of intellectual inquiry as falling
into distinct disciplines.
He insists, for instance, that the standards of proof and evidence for deductive logic and
mathematics should not be applied to the study of nature, and that neither of these disciplines should be taken as a
proper model for moral and political inquiry.
He distinguishes philosophical reflection on a discipline from the practice
of the discipline itself.
The corpus contains contributions to many different disciplines, not only to philosophy.
Some
areas of inquiry in which Aristotle makes a fundamental contribution are these: (1) Logic.
Aristotle's Prior Analytics
constitutes the first attempt to formulate a system of deductive formal logic, based on the theory of the 'syllogism'.
The Posterior Analytics uses this system to formulate an account of rigorous scientific knowledge.
'Logic', as
Aristotle conceives it, also includes the study of language, meaning and their relation to non-linguistic reality; hence
it includes many topics that might now be assigned to philosophy of language or philosophical logic (Categories, De
Interpretatione, Topics).
(2) The study of nature.
About a quarter of the corpus (see especially the History of
Animals, Parts of Animals, and Generation of Animals; also Movement of Animals, Progression of Animals) consists of
works concerned with biology.
Some of these contain collections of detailed observations.
(The Meteorology
contains a similar collection on inanimate nature.) Others try to explain these observations in the light of the
explanatory scheme that Aristotle defends in his more theoretical reflections on the study of nature.
These
reflections (especially in the Physics and in Generation and Corruption) develop an account of nature, form, matter,
cause and change that expresses Aristotle's views about the understanding and explanation of natural organisms
and their behaviour.
Natural philosophy and cosmology are combined in On the Heavens.
(3) Metaphysics.
In his
reflections on the foundations and presuppositions of other disciplines, Aristotle describes a universal 'science of
being qua being', the concern of the Metaphysics.
Part of this universal science examines the foundations of inquiry
into nature.
Aristotle formulates his doctrine of substance, which he explains through the connected contrasts
between form and matter, and between potentiality and actuality.
One of his aims is to describe the distinctive and
irreducible character of living organisms.
Another aim of the universal science is to use his examination of substance
to give an account of divine substance, the ultimate principle of the cosmic order.
(4) Philosophy of mind.
The
doctrine of form and matter is used to explain the relation of soul and body, and the different types of soul found in
different types of living creatures.
In Aristotle's view, the soul is the form of a living body.
He examines the different
aspects of this form in plants, non-rational animals and human beings, by describing nutrition, perception, thought
and desire.
His discussion (in On the Soul, and also in the Parva Naturalia) ranges over topics in philosophy of mind,
psychology, physiology, epistemology and theory of action.
(5) Ethics and politics (Nicomachean Ethics, Eudemian
Ethics, Magna Moralia).
In Aristotle's view, the understanding of the natural and essential aims of human agents is
the right basis for a grasp of principles guiding moral and political practice.
These principles are expressed in his
account of human wellbeing, and of the different virtues that constitute a good person and promote wellbeing.
The
description of a society that embodies these virtues in individual and social life is a task for the Politics, which also
examines the virtues and vices of actual states and societies, measuring them against the principles derived from
ethical theory.
(6) Literary criticism and rhetorical theory (Poetics, Rhetoric).
These works are closely connected
both to Aristotle's logic and to his ethical and political theory.
1 Life Aristotle was born in 384 BC, in the
Macedonian city of Stagira, now part of northern Greece.
In his lifetime the kingdom of Macedon, first under Philip
and then under Philip's son Alexander ('the Great'), conquered both the Greek cities of Europe and Asia and the
Persian Empire.
Although Aristotle spent much of his adult life in Athens, he was not an Athenian citizen.
He was
closely linked to the kings of Macedon, whom many Greeks regarded as foreign invaders; hence, he was affected by
the volatile relations between Macedon and the Greek cities, especially Athens.
Aristotle was the son of
Nicomachus, a doctor attached to the Macedonian court.
In 367 BC Aristotle came to Athens.
He belonged to
Plato's Academy until the death of Plato in 347; during these years Plato wrote his important later dialogues
(including the Sophist, Timaeus, Philebus, Statesman, and Laws), which reconsider many of the doctrines of his
earlier dialogues and pursue new lines of thought.
Since there was no dogmatic system of 'Platonism', Aristotle was
neither a disciple of such a system nor a rebel against it.
The exploratory and critical outlook of the Academy
probably encouraged Aristotle's own philosophical growth.
In 347 BC Aristotle left Athens, for Assos in Asia Minor.
Later he moved to Lesbos, in the eastern Aegean, and then to Macedon, where he was a tutor of Alexander.
In 334
he returned to Athens and founded his own school, the Lyceum.
In 323 Alexander died; in the resulting outbreak of
anti-Macedonian feeling in Athens Aristotle left for Chalcis, on the island of Euboea, where he died in 322.
Aristotle
married Pythias, a niece of Hermeias, the ruler of Assos.
They had a daughter, also called Pythias.
After the death
of his wife, Aristotle formed an attachment to Herpyllis, and they had a son Nicomachus.
2 Order of Aristotle's
works By the end of Aristotle's life the Lyceum must have become a well-established school.
It lasted after
Aristotle's death; his successor as head of the school was his pupil Theophrastus.
Many of the works in the
Aristotelian corpus appear to be closely related to Aristotle's lectures in the Lyceum.
The polished character of
some passages suggests preparation for publication (for example, Parts of Animals I 5), but many passages contain
incomplete sentences and compressed allusions, suggesting notes that a lecturer might expand (for example,
Metaphysics VII 13).
We cannot tell how many of his treatises Aristotle regarded as 'finished' (see §11 on the
Metaphysics and §21 on the Ethics).
It may be wrong, therefore, to ask about the 'date' of a particular treatise.
If
Aristotle neither published nor intended to publish the treatises, a given treatise may easily contain contributions
from different dates.
For similar reasons, we cannot plausibly take cross-references from one work to another as
evidence of the order of the works.
External, biographical considerations are unhelpful, since we lack the evidence.
»
↓↓↓ APERÇU DU DOCUMENT ↓↓↓