Aristotelianism, Renaissance
Extrait du document
One of the issues discussed by medieval Aristotelians that continued to concern Aristotelian philosophers during the Renaissance was the identification of the subject of natural philosophy. This issue was thought to be important because it concerned not only the relationship between metaphysics (the science of being qua being) and natural philosophy, but also the place of immaterial created beings, such as angels, within Aristotelian science. Thomas Aquinas (§9) had argued that mobile or changeable being (ens mobile), which seems to include all beings liable to change (that is, everything other than God), was the subject of natural philosophy, whereas his teacher Albert the Great (§4) took it to be mobile or changeable body (corpus mobile). Later, Paul of Venice states that the subject matter is natural body (corpus naturale), while his student, Cajetan of Thiene (Gaetano da Thiene) (1387-1485), maintained that it is sensible substance (substantia sensibilis). Subsequently the whole issue was approached in a systematic fashion by Cajetan's student, Nicoletto Vernia (§3), who composed a separate question on whether mobile being is the subject of all natural philosophy. In it he reviews and compares a wide range of authors including Antonius Andreas and John Canonicus, whom he attacks for judging Aristotle to have erred in natural philosophy. Vernia accuses them of not speaking naturally but rather introducing theological considerations into the discussion, namely the question of the motion of angels. Vernia himself upholds and defends mobile being as the subject, which he took to be the position of Averroes. Thereafter Vernia's student Agostino Nifo (§2) took up the question of the subject matter of natural philosophy in his commentary on the Physics.
«
Aristotelianism, Renaissance By the Renaissance here is meant the period of the fifteenth and sixteenth
centuries during which there was a deliberate attempt, especially in Italy, to pattern cultural activities on models
drawn from antiquity.
However, Aristotelianism during that period was not cut off from medieval developments, since
earlier interests and topics of discussion still held the attention of philosophers, theologians and non-academic
intellectuals.
Moreover, given that Aristotelianism was embedded in the university curriculum, the approach and
activities of Renaissance Aristotelians often reflected earlier institutional developments.
The educational reforms of
the German Lutheran Philipp Melanchthon and of the newly-founded Society of Jesus (the Jesuits) ensured that
Aristotle remained central to the curriculum.
On the other hand, deliberate attempts to divorce themselves from
earlier structures and approaches can be discerned in some Renaissance Aristotelians.
Owing to the influence of
humanism, professors of philosophy whose loyalty was to Aristotle came to study Greek and explicate Aristotle from
the Greek text, to imitate the style of classical models, and to prefer the Greek commentators over the medieval
Latins because their language was Greek.
Renaissance Aristotelianism did not constitute a uniform, coherent school
of thought with a clearly defined body of doctrines shared by all adherents.
A careful reading of the many
commentaries, paraphrases, textbooks and treatises based on Aristotle's works reveals a surprisingly wide variation
in interpretation and a strong tendency to modify or supplement the Stagirite's teachings with tenets derived from
other philosophical or scientific sources or from contemporary interests and discoveries.
It is perhaps wise to speak
of a variety of Aristotelianisms rather than to perpetuate the long-standing caricature of 'modern' philosophy and
science arising by throwing off the shackles of a monolithic Peripatetic orthodoxy.
The various Aristotelianisms
included Albertism, Thomism, Scotism and Averroism, but as a result of the new translations of the Greek
commentators on Aristotle there were also Renaissance Aristotelians who approached Aristotle by way of Alexander
of Aphrodisias, Themistius, Simplicius and John Philoponus.
Another current is best described as 'eclectic
Aristotelianism'.
Some Aristotelians adopted a 'philological' approach, approaching Aristotle simply through analysis of
the Greek text and not as a philosophical challenge.
This approach made Aristotelianism irrelevant to the enterprise
of philosophy, but fortunately did not predominate.
1 Aristotle, the Greek text and the Greek commentators
Although Aristotle was accorded the honorific title of 'The Philosopher' by most philosopher-theologians of the high
Middle Ages (see Aristotelianism, medieval), there were also some who viewed him far less favourably.
The
fourteenth-century Franciscans Francis of Meyronnes, Antonius Andreas and John Canonicus carried Bonaventure's
critique of Aristotle to its ultimate conclusion (see Bonaventure).
The first called Aristotle 'the worst metaphysician',
and both Andreas and Canonicus viewed him as a poor natural philosopher.
Their critical views were known to
Renaissance Aristotelians like Nicoletto Vernia, Agostino Nifo and Marcantonio Zimara (c.1475-1532).
Nevertheless,
Aristotle's influence on philosophy and science during the Renaissance was profound.
Both his own works and those
of his many late ancient and medieval interpreters attracted a wide audience.
His writings on logic and natural
philosophy formed the centrepiece of university studies in the arts and provided essential preparation for a career in
medicine, law or theology, while his works on ethics, poetics and politics were widely read and discussed by a
learned public increasingly educated in the schools of the humanists.
Despite the emphasis given to Renaissance
Platonism in general histories of culture, a survey of the philosophical and scientific literature actually produced
during the period from 1400 to 1600 clearly establishes the Renaissance as a golden age in the history of
Aristotelianism.
Since Renaissance philosophers trained in the arts faculties of major European universities had
normally received a thorough grounding in Aristotle, those who became professors in their own right for the most
part continued to base their instruction on the Aristotelian corpus.
Their writings often reflected this, taking the
form of commentaries on Aristotle, though works devoted to the systematic exposition of a particular topic - such
as Pietro Pomponazzi's famous treatise De immortalitate animae (On the Immortality of the Soul) (1516) or Jacopo
Zabarella's De naturalis scientiae constitutione (On the Nature of Natural Science) (published in 1586) - were not
infrequent, particularly when aimed at a general learned audience rather than at other scholars (see Pomponazzi, P.
§2; Zabarella, J.
§6).
Aristotle's dominance among university professors withstood the challenge mounted by the
handful of appointments of chairs of Platonic philosophy in Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Version 1.0,
London and New York: Routledge (1998) Aristotelianism, Renaissance Italy (see Platonism, Renaissance §5).
Much of
the continued predominance of Aristotle was due to the work of humanists, their knowledge of Greek, and the new
critical techniques they developed.
The Greek text of Aristotle's works was published, notably in the edition of
1495-8 printed by Aldo Manuzio.
New translations were done, and from the 1530s onward, bilingual editions were
produced.
From 1499 onward, but especially in the 1520s and 1530s, editions of the Greek commentators on
Aristotle were printed, and these in turn were translated, many for the first time.
Nor was attention paid only to the
Greek commentators, for in 1483 Nicoletto Vernia edited an important Aristotle-Averroes edition, and 1550-2 saw
the great Giunta Aristotle-Averroes edition containing many works not previously included.
The Aristotle
commentaries of such medieval Latin authors as Albert the Great and Thomas Aquinas were also printed.
At the
same time, attention was paid to the canon of Aristotle's work.
Many dubious and spurious works had been excluded
by 1600.
On the other hand, the Poetics, which had been little read during the Middle Ages, came to have a great
influence on literary criticism, and the pseudo-Aristotelian Mechanics also attracted a good deal of attention.
2
Logic and method Renaissance Aristotelians developed an account of scientific methodology that built on insights
put forward by Aristotle (§6) in his Posterior Analytics and Physics.
In a well-known passage in the Posterior
Analytics Aristotle distinguishes between two types of demonstration.
The first he calls demonstration of the fact
(to hoti) or demonstration quia.
Its primary characteristic is that the middle terms of such demonstrations tell us
only the fact that something is the case and not why this is the case.
The second type of demonstration has a
middle term that tells us the reason why (to dioti).
Medieval thinkers inspired by this analysis connected Aristotle's
remarks on demonstration with his remarks at the beginning of the Physics concerning the proper method for
establishing the principles of nature.
There Aristotle claims that one should start with those things that are more
knowable to us and proceed to those things more knowable or intelligible by nature, though not to us.
In addition,
some later thinkers equated two methods set forth by Galen (§§3-4) with the two sorts of demonstration.
In his Art.
»
↓↓↓ APERÇU DU DOCUMENT ↓↓↓